Immediate and Mediated Existence
(an essay submitted for the Philosophy of Language class)
Preliminary Considerations
This essay started as a more focused and simple investigation into Donnellan’s “Reference and Definite Descriptions” paper. However, as it is often the case, things plugged in quickly into former research, generating a quite different, more complex, and possibly confusing at times, essay.
I was considering whether to submit just a truncated but more polished version for our colloquium, limited to Donnellan’s paper, or the entire thing as is right now. I have decided to go on with the entire draft even if it still needs lots of work, mainly because I wanted to have the opportunity for some early feedback.
3. Quine’s Attempted Resolution
3.1 The Initial Problem
Quine begins “On What There Is”5 with the main puzzle of the non-existents that drived Russell’s paper, but using a different angle: how can we meaningfully deny that things exist? If we say “Pegasus does not exist,” we face a paradox:
5 (Quine 1948)
“If Pegasus were not, McX argues, we should not be talking about anything when we use the word; therefore it would be nonsense to say even that Pegasus is not” (Quine, 1948)
This leads Quine to examine two failed solutions. McX argues that if we can talk about something, it must somehow exist. Yet as Quine notes, McX himself:
“cannot, indeed, quite persuade himself that any region of space-time, near or remote, contains a flying horse of flesh and blood.”
He then proceeds to dismiss Wyman’s solution of “subsistence6 vs existence” on obvious grounds.
6 It’s relevant to mention that the ideea of “subsistence” and “existence” as two different kinds of being, was developed by Meinong in 1904 and this was known to Russell who in “On Denoting”, in a footnote to a paragraph mentioning Meinong (Russell 1905, 485), says “I use these [subsistence or being] as synonym” (see quote in §2). Wyman’s view, quoted by Quine, is actually Meinong’s original view. Moreover, the whole example quine is using is echoing Russell’s arguments about Meinong’s theory.
3.2 The Logical Solution
Quine resolves this conundrum by extending Russell’s theory of descriptions in a crucial way. While Russell had shown how definite descriptions could be analyzed without assuming existence, Quine goes further by showing how any name can be systematically converted into a description through a corresponding predicate - “Pegasus” becomes “the thing that Pegasizes.”
This is significant because: 1. It generalizes Russell’s solution beyond explicit descriptions to all names 2. It preserves the logical structure of Russell’s analysis while expanding its scope 3. It provides a uniform treatment of existence claims, whether they involve descriptions or names For example, “Pegasus does not exist” becomes “It is not the case that there exists an x such that x Pegasizes” - formally: ~∃x(Px). This eliminates the apparent paradox of referring to something while denying its existence.
3.3 The Ontological Commitment
This conversion of names to descriptions fundamentally changes how we handle existence claims. By transforming proper names into predicates that can be quantified over, Quine shifts the question from whether individual named entities exist to what kinds of things our statements commit us to accepting as existent. If ‘Pegasus’ becomes ‘the thing that Pegasizes,’ we can analyze the ontological implications of our statements about Pegasus without assuming its existence. Building on this logical foundation, Quine establishes a broader criterion for determining what entities we are committed to including in our ontology:
“We commit ourselves to an ontology containing centaurs when we say there are centaurs… But we do not commit ourselves to an ontology containing Pegasus or the author of Waverly or the round square cupola on Berkeley College when we say that Pegasus or the author of Waverly or the cupola in question is not.”
4. Donnellan’s Attributive and Refferential DD
1. The distinction
Donnellan goes in detail in his paper over both “On Denoting” of Russell’s and “On Refering” of Strawson to argue that both actually missed the referring function of DDs, and ends up by identifying two uses of definite descriptions:
“I will call the two uses of definite descriptions I have in mind the attributive use and the referential use. A speaker who uses a definite description attributively in an assertion states something about whoever or whatever is the so-and-so. A speaker who uses a definite description referentially in an assertion, on the other hand, uses the description to enable his audience to pick out whom or what he is talking about and states something about that person or thing.” (Keith S. Donnellan, 1966, p. 285)
This is the key phrase. One thing to be noted is the referential use, when employed to objects in direct proximity, can be substituted entirely by pointing out, without any uttering, while the attributive use is relying entirely on language. This points (no pun intended) to some way we use existence claims in some sort of pre-verbal manner, one that is not accounted for by Russell’s DDs but can be included in what Donnellan calls “referential use”. Pointing is actually a referring gesture.
2. Smith’s murderer
To make the idea clearer, let’s take Donellan example: “Smith’s murderer is insane”. When we know nothing about the murderer, only that Smith was fouly murdered, we infer his the existence using a tipical DD, Donaldson calls “attributive”. But when we know him (it’s Jones), we use the DD “Smith’s Murderer” to refer to Jones, not to an abstract concept.
If I try to keep silent and still transmit “Smith’s murderer is insane”, I can’t manage to do it in the first case mainly because I need to translate concepts into gestures, something hardly possible without loosing all details; in the second case, however, it is enough that I discretely point with my head and eyes to Jones on the trial stand and make a significant gesture with my hand at my temple.
This difference maps precisely onto Russell’s notion of acquaintance: referential use requires what Russell called “acquaintance” — direct perceptual access to what we’re talking about. When we can use a description referentially, we are in a position of acquaintance with its object. When we can only use it attributively, we lack this direct access and must rely on pure description.
5. Immediate(ed) and Mediated Existence
1. Hintikka’s formalism
Hintikka introduced in “Knowledge and Belief” (Hintikka, Hendricks, and Symons 2005) a couple of logical operators to try to discern among different epistemological operations, Ka → “a knows that”, Ba → “a believes that”, together with a fundamental principle that knowledge implies truth (Kap → p). This approach is interesting because it shows how the nuances of our relationship to the world can be formalized in logical language. I am mentioning it also because some readers will be inclined to draw an analogy with it.
While our approach draws inspiration from Hintikka’s epistemic logic, the quantifiers we will introduce serve a very different purpose because they do not deal with knowledge conditions.They simply mark different grounds for existence claims, acknowledging the different way in which we currently make existence claims, without implying different kinds of knowledge.
2. Two new existential quantifiers
Keeping in mind the distinction we draw from the works of Russel, Quine and Donnellan, i.e. that attributive and referential DD point to two separate kinds of ontological claim, we’ll define a new kind of existential quantifier, ending up with two existential quantifiers:
- inverted ∃, standing for what we will call “mediated existence” - that which exists through language and concepts
- simple E, standing for what we’ll call “immediate existence” - that which exists in direct, pre-linguistic experience
“Mediated” here points to the crucial role of language in making something accessible to thought. In this sense, all logical existence is mediated through language (thus the inverted ∃ is inevitable in logic), while “real” existence is immediate, prior to and independent of linguistic conceptualization.9
9 The mediated and immediated existence quantifiers clarify the problem in Quine’s assertion that “something exists if it’s the value of a bound variable”: Quine is clearly taking here only about mediated existence, while all possible coutner-examples are about immediated existence.
To clarify their relationship, we’ll examine the §3 counter-examples to Quine and reveal different patterns of interaction between immediate and mediated existence:
Cloaked Parthenon (p):
- before cloaking:
Ep & ∃p
(both immediately experienced and linguistically mediated) - after cloaking:
¬Ep & ∃p
(linguistically mediated but not immediately experienced)
Twin towers(tt):
- pre 2001:
Ett & ∃tt
(both immediate and mediated existence) - post 2001:
¬Ett & ∃tt
(persisting in language while vanishing from immediate experience)
Optical illusion (for object o): Eo & ¬∃o
(immediately experienced but lacking mediated existence - pure phenomenon without conceptual reality)
At the edges of this framework, we find particularly revealing cases:
Pure concepts (justice j): ¬Ej & ∃j
(exists only through language, no immediate experience possible)
Pain (p):
- Raw experience:
Ep & ¬∃p
(pure immediate existence before conceptualization) - Once named:
Ep & ∃p
(both immediate and linguistically mediated)
Virtual Reality (v):
- The experience:
Ev & ¬∃v
(immediately experienced but lacking mediated existence when knowing it is virtual?) - The technology:
¬Eh & ∃h
(exists conceptually but not immediately experienced)
Dreams (d):
- During:
Ed & ¬∃d
(pure immediate experience) - After waking:
¬Ed & ∃d
(transformed into linguistic/conceptual existence)
These patterns reveal something fundamental about how experience and language interact in creating our understanding of existence.
Important note on the two existence quantifiers
While our notation might suggest two types of existence, this would lead us into murky metaphysical waters. Instead, E and inverted ∃ should be understood as operators marking different grounds for using “exists” in language. When we say Em & ∃m
, we’re not claiming the mountain exists in two different ways, but rather noting that our use of “exists” here can be grounded both in immediate experience and in conceptual frameworks. Similarly, when we write ¬Ej & ∃j
for justice, we’re marking that our use of “exists” here can only be grounded in conceptual frameworks, not in immediate experience.
It may help to remind that E and inverted ∃ mark different grounds for existence claims without implying different kinds of knowledge. From an epistemic standpoint, whether we assert existence through immediate experience or through conceptual mediation, we are making the same type of claim - that something “is”. The distinction lies not in different modes of knowing but in different contexts of usage, somewhat analogous to, though more formally specified than, Wittgenstein’s analysis of how words function in different language games.
Maybe the most important difference about the two operators is that immediate existence (E) points to a pre-linguistic modality of understanding existence: being aware of the mountain in front of me (Em) does not need any sort of conceptualization; immediate existence is the ‘primitive’ ancestor of mediated existence. There is here an interesting connection to Heidegger’s Being and Time argument about how our practical engagement with things (what he calls “ready-to-hand”) precedes theoretical, predicative understanding.
This clarification maintains the analytical utility of our notation, while avoiding both metaphysical claims about types of existence and epistemological claims about types of knowledge.
6. Addressing some possible connections
There are some possible connections one can do on this very early draft.
1. Kripke’s critique of Donnellan:
A Kripkean critique might argue that the distinction between referential and attributive uses is purely pragmatic, not semantic. When we say ‘Smith’s murderer is insane’ while pointing at Jones in the dock, we’re simply using language improperly - the semantic content remains tied to whoever actually murdered Smith, while the speaker’s reference happens to pick out Jones. This suggests no deep distinction in types of existence claims, merely different pragmatic uses of the same semantic tools.
However, this critique misses how existence claims operate at a more fundamental level than reference. When we point to Jones in the dock, we’re grounding our existence claim in immediate experience (E), while the phrase ‘Smith’s murderer’ operates through mediated existence (∃). Words, by their nature, always function within mediated existence — they are the mediating device themselves. The confusion Kripke identifies arises precisely because we’re attempting to bridge immediate experience with linguistic mediation. This suggests reference problems aren’t merely pragmatic issues but reflect a deeper distinction in how we ground existence claims.
2. Kit Fine’s “wordly” and “unwordly” entities
Fine’s ‘Problem of Possibilia’ (2003) presents a sophisticated modal account distinguishing between ‘worldly’ things that exist in possible worlds and ‘unworldly’ entities that exist through conceptual necessity. This distinction resonates with but differs from our framework of immediated and mediated existence. Where Fine requires complex modal logic to handle possibilia, our distinction between E and ∃ quantifiers offers a more direct formalization of how existence claims function in natural language.
For instance, while Fine must construct elaborate modal frameworks to explain how fictional entities like Sherlock Holmes can be said to exist, our framework simply notes that such entities have mediated existence (∃) without immediate existence (E). This parallels everyday linguistic practice where we comfortably say both that ‘Sherlock Holmes exists in Conan Doyle’s stories’ (∃) while acknowledging he doesn’t exist in immediate experience (¬E). The framework thus captures intuitive distinctions that Fine approaches through more complex theoretical machinery.